Composition

Posted on 2018-02-19 by nbloomf
Tags: arithmetic-made-difficult, literate-haskell

This page is part of a series on Arithmetic Made Difficult.

This post is literate Haskell; you can load the source into GHCi and play along.


{-# LANGUAGE NoImplicitPrelude #-}
module Composition
  ( compose2on1, compose3on1
  , compose1on2, compose2on2
  , compose1on3
  , compose1on4
  , _test_compose, main_compose
  ) where

import Testing
import Functions
import Flip

We can think of \(\compose(f)(g)(x)\) as taking an outer function \(f\) of one argument, and another function \(g\) that massages some input \(x\) before passing it on to \(f\). We can express more complicated compositions of functions by stacking \(\compose\) on itself in various ways – but to avoid keeping track of too many \(\compose\)s it will be handy to generalize to some named operators. Say \(f\) takes two arguments; a generalized compose for such a function might take two different input-massaging functions \(g\) and \(h\), and two inputs \(x\) and \(y\), and pass \(g(x)\) and \(h(y)\) to \(f\), like \[\Theta(f)(g)(h)(x)(y) = f(g(x))(h(y)).\] We can do exactly this with \(\composeBonA\).

We define \[\composeBonA : (C \rightarrow D \rightarrow E) \rightarrow (A \rightarrow C) \rightarrow (B \rightarrow D) \rightarrow A \rightarrow B \rightarrow E\] by \[\composeBonA = \flipC(\compose(\compose(\compose(\compose)))(\compose))\]

In Haskell:

\(\composeBonA\) does what we want:

When the signatures of \(f\), \(g\), and \(h\) make sense, we have \[\composeBonA(f)(g)(h)(x)(y) = f(g(x))(h(y)).\]

We have \[\begin{eqnarray*} & & \composeBonA(f)(g)(h)(x)(y) \\ & \href{/posts/arithmetic-made-difficult/Composition.html#def-compose2on1} = & \flipC(\compose(\compose(\compose(\compose)))(\compose))(f)(g)(h)(x)(y) \\ & \href{/posts/arithmetic-made-difficult/Flip.html#thm-flip3} = & \compose(\compose(\compose(\compose)))(\compose)(f)(g)(x)(h)(y) \\ & \href{/posts/arithmetic-made-difficult/Functions.html#def-compose} = & \compose(\compose(\compose))(\compose(f))(g)(x)(h)(y) \\ & \href{/posts/arithmetic-made-difficult/Functions.html#def-compose} = & \compose(\compose)(\compose(f)(g))(x)(h)(y) \\ & \href{/posts/arithmetic-made-difficult/Functions.html#def-compose} = & \compose(\compose(f)(g)(x))(h)(y) \\ & \href{/posts/arithmetic-made-difficult/Functions.html#def-compose} = & \compose(f(g(x)))(h)(y) \\ & \href{/posts/arithmetic-made-difficult/Functions.html#def-compose} = & f(g(x))(h(y)) \end{eqnarray*}\] as claimed.

Generalizing further, \(\composeConA\) acts on a function of three arguments.

We define \[\begin{eqnarray*} \composeConA & : & (D \rightarrow E \rightarrow F \rightarrow G) \\ & & \rightarrow (A \rightarrow D) \\ & & \rightarrow (B \rightarrow E) \\ & & \rightarrow (C \rightarrow F) \\ & & \rightarrow A \rightarrow B \rightarrow C \rightarrow G \end{eqnarray*}\] by \[\composeConA = \flipD(\flipE(\flipC(\compose(\compose(\compose(\compose(\compose(\compose)))))(\compose(\compose(\compose(\compose)))(\compose)))))\]

In Haskell:

And \(\composeConA\) does what we want.

Whenever the signatures of \(f\), \(g\), \(h\), and \(k\) make sense, we have \[\compose3(f)(g)(h)(k)(x)(y)(z) = f(g(x))(h(y))(k(z)).\]

We have \[\begin{eqnarray*} & & \composeConA(f)(g)(h)(k)(x)(y)(z) \\ & \href{/posts/arithmetic-made-difficult/Composition.html#def-compose3on1} = & \flipD(\flipE(\flipC(\compose(\compose(\compose(\compose(\compose(\compose)))))(\compose(\compose(\compose(\compose)))(\compose)))))(f)(g)(h)(k)(x)(y)(z) \\ & \href{/posts/arithmetic-made-difficult/Flip.html#thm-flip4} = & \flipE(\flipC(\compose(\compose(\compose(\compose(\compose(\compose)))))(\compose(\compose(\compose(\compose)))(\compose))))(f)(g)(h)(x)(k)(y)(z) \\ & \href{/posts/arithmetic-made-difficult/Flip.html#thm-flip5} = & \flipC(\compose(\compose(\compose(\compose(\compose(\compose)))))(\compose(\compose(\compose(\compose)))(\compose)))(f)(g)(h)(x)(y)(k)(z) \\ & \href{/posts/arithmetic-made-difficult/Flip.html#thm-flip3} = & \compose(\compose(\compose(\compose(\compose(\compose)))))(\compose(\compose(\compose(\compose)))(\compose))(f)(g)(x)(h)(y)(k)(z) \\ & \href{/posts/arithmetic-made-difficult/Functions.html#def-compose} = & \compose(\compose(\compose(\compose(\compose))))(\compose(\compose(\compose(\compose)))(\compose)(f))(g)(x)(h)(y)(k)(z) \\ & \href{/posts/arithmetic-made-difficult/Functions.html#def-compose} = & \compose(\compose(\compose(\compose)))(\compose(\compose(\compose(\compose)))(\compose)(f)(g))(x)(h)(y)(k)(z) \\ & \href{/posts/arithmetic-made-difficult/Functions.html#def-compose} = & \compose(\compose(\compose))(\compose(\compose(\compose(\compose)))(\compose)(f)(g)(x))(h)(y)(k)(z) \\ & \href{/posts/arithmetic-made-difficult/Functions.html#def-compose} = & \compose(\compose)(\compose(\compose(\compose(\compose)))(\compose)(f)(g)(x)(h))(y)(k)(z) \\ & \href{/posts/arithmetic-made-difficult/Functions.html#def-compose} = & \compose(\compose(\compose(\compose(\compose)))(\compose)(f)(g)(x)(h)(y))(k)(z) \\ & \href{/posts/arithmetic-made-difficult/Functions.html#def-compose} = & \compose(\compose(\compose(\compose)))(\compose)(f)(g)(x)(h)(y)(k(z)) \\ & \href{/posts/arithmetic-made-difficult/Functions.html#def-compose} = & \compose(\compose(\compose))(\compose(f))(g)(x)(h)(y)(k(z)) \\ & \href{/posts/arithmetic-made-difficult/Functions.html#def-compose} = & \compose(\compose)(\compose(f)(g))(x)(h)(y)(k(z)) \\ & \href{/posts/arithmetic-made-difficult/Functions.html#def-compose} = & \compose(\compose(f)(g)(x))(h)(y)(k(z)) \\ & \href{/posts/arithmetic-made-difficult/Functions.html#def-compose} = & \compose(f)(g)(x)(h(y))(k(z)) \\ & \href{/posts/arithmetic-made-difficult/Functions.html#def-compose} = & f(g(x))(h(y))(k(z)) \end{eqnarray*}\] as claimed.

A really good question to ask at this point is, “where on earth did those definitions for \(\composeBonA\) and \(\composeConA\) come from?” It’s almost certainly not obvious how we could write such a thing down without already knowing some trick. And there is a trick – it turns out we can calculate these definitions, and others, using the known properties of our function operators. Take \(\composeBonA\) for example. Say we’re setting out to find a definition for the map \(\Theta(f)(g)(h)(x)(y) = f(g(x))(h(y))\). First off, I know from experience that (1) with \(\compose\), we can move function arguments in and out of parentheses as long as they’re in the right order, and (2) putting the arguments of a function in any given order is easy with \(\flip\) and friends. So we might as well start out looking for \(\Theta\) such that \[\Theta(f)(g)(x)(h)(y) = f(g(x))(h(y)),\] since we can apply an appropriate sequence of \(\flip\)s to \(\Theta\) at the end.

Now, working backwards, start with \[f(g(x))(h(y)).\] Note that this fits the pattern of a \(\compose\), where the outer function is \(f(g(x))\), and the inner function is \(h\). So this expression is equivalent to \[\compose(f(g(x)))(h)(y).\] We’ve peeled off the last two arguments of \(\Theta\) already. We’d like to peel off the next argument from the right; in this case, \(x\). Imagine that the \(x\) argument is trapped inside two extra sets of parentheses. And the tool for eliminating parentheses is \(\compose\). Indeed, we can write \(f(g(x)) = \compose(f)(g)(x)\), and now \(x\) is “lifted up” by one level. So our expression is now equivalent to \[\compose(\compose(f)(g)(x))(h)(y).\] We can play this game again; \(x\) is still trapped, and is the argument of a composition where the outer function is \(\compose\) and the inner function is \(\compose(f)(g)\). So our expression is equivalent to \[\compose(\compose)(\compose(f)(g))(x)(h)(y).\] We can see the trick now; \(g\) is trapped, and another \(\compose\) gives \[\compose(\compose(\compose))(\compose(f))(g)(x)(h)(y).\] Now \(f\) is trapped, but another \(\compose\) gives \[\compose(\compose(\compose(\compose)))(\compose)(f)(g)(x)(h)(y).\] So we have \[\Theta = \compose(\compose(\compose(\compose)))(\compose),\] and applying a \(\flipC\) to this map gives the \(\compose2\) we defined above.

A similar trick applies when we want to use some input more than once; this time we assume that an appropriate \(\clone\) has been applied.

Two more generalizations of \(\compose\) will also be handy.

We define \[\composeAonB : (C \rightarrow D) \rightarrow (A \rightarrow B \rightarrow C) \rightarrow A \rightarrow B \rightarrow D\] by \[\composeAonB = \compose(\compose)(\compose)\]

In Haskell:

And \(\composeAonB\) behaves like so:

We have \[\composeAonB(f)(g)(x)(y) = f(g(x)(y)).\]

Note that \[\begin{eqnarray*} & & \composeAonB(f)(g)(x)(y) \\ & \href{/posts/arithmetic-made-difficult/Composition.html#def-compose1on2} = & \compose(\compose)(\compose)(f)(g)(x)(y) \\ & \href{/posts/arithmetic-made-difficult/Functions.html#def-compose} = & \compose(\compose(f))(g)(x)(y) \\ & \href{/posts/arithmetic-made-difficult/Functions.html#def-compose} = & \compose(f)(g(x))(y) \\ & \href{/posts/arithmetic-made-difficult/Functions.html#def-compose} = & f(g(x)(y)) \end{eqnarray*}\] as claimed.

Now:

We define \[\composeAonC : (D \rightarrow E) \rightarrow (A \rightarrow B \rightarrow C \rightarrow D) \rightarrow A \rightarrow B \rightarrow C \rightarrow E\] by \[\composeAonC = \compose(\compose)(\composeAonB)\]

In Haskell:

And \(\composeAonC\) behaves like so:

We have \[\composeAonC(f)(g)(x)(y)(z) = f(g(x)(y)(z)).\]

Note that \[\begin{eqnarray*} & & \composeAonC(f)(g)(x)(y)(z) \\ & \href{/posts/arithmetic-made-difficult/Composition.html#def-compose1on3} = & \compose(\compose)(\composeAonB)(f)(g)(x)(y)(z) \\ & \href{/posts/arithmetic-made-difficult/Functions.html#def-compose} = & \compose(\composeAonB(f))(g)(x)(y)(z) \\ & \href{/posts/arithmetic-made-difficult/Functions.html#def-compose} = & \composeAonB(f)(g(x))(y)(z) \\ & \href{/posts/arithmetic-made-difficult/Composition.html#thm-compose1on2} = & f(g(x)(y)(z)) \end{eqnarray*}\] as claimed.

Now:

We define \[\composeAonD : (E \rightarrow F) \rightarrow (A \rightarrow B \rightarrow C \rightarrow D \rightarrow E) \rightarrow A \rightarrow B \rightarrow C \rightarrow D \rightarrow F\] by \[\composeAonD = \compose(\compose)(\composeAonC)\]

In Haskell:

And \(\composeAonD\) behaves like so:

We have \[\composeAonD(f)(g)(x)(y)(z)(w) = f(g(x)(y)(z)(w)).\]

Note that \[\begin{eqnarray*} & & \composeAonD(f)(g)(x)(y)(z)(w) \\ & \href{/posts/arithmetic-made-difficult/Composition.html#def-compose1on4} = & \compose(\compose)(\composeAonC)(f)(g)(x)(y)(z)(w) \\ & \href{/posts/arithmetic-made-difficult/Functions.html#def-compose} = & \compose(\composeAonC(f))(g)(x)(y)(z)(w) \\ & \href{/posts/arithmetic-made-difficult/Functions.html#def-compose} = & \composeAonC(f)(g(x))(y)(z)(w) \\ & \href{/posts/arithmetic-made-difficult/Composition.html#thm-compose1on3} = & f(g(x)(y)(z)(w)) \end{eqnarray*}\] as claimed.

Now:

We define \[\begin{eqnarray*} \composeBonB & : & (E \rightarrow F \rightarrow G) \\ & & \rightarrow (A \rightarrow B \rightarrow E) \\ & & \rightarrow (C \rightarrow D \rightarrow F) \\ & & \rightarrow A \rightarrow B \rightarrow C \rightarrow D \rightarrow G \end{eqnarray*}\] by \[\composeBonB = \]

In Haskell:

And \(\composeBonB\) behaves like so:

We have \[\composeBonB(f)(g)(h)(x)(y)(z)(w) = f(g(x)(y))(h(z)(w)).\]

Note that \[\begin{eqnarray*} & & \composeBonB(f)(g)(h)(x)(y)(z)(w) \\ & \href{/posts/arithmetic-made-difficult/Composition.html#def-compose2on2} = & \flipE(\compose(\composeBonA)(\composeBonA))(f)(g)(h)(x)(y)(z)(w) \\ & \href{/posts/arithmetic-made-difficult/Flip.html#thm-flip5} = & \compose(\composeBonA)(\composeBonA)(f)(g)(h)(x)(z)(y)(w) \\ & \href{/posts/arithmetic-made-difficult/Functions.html#def-compose} = & \composeBonA(\composeBonA(f))(g)(h)(x)(z)(y)(w) \\ & \href{/posts/arithmetic-made-difficult/Composition.html#thm-compose2on1} = & \composeBonA(f)(g(x))(h(z))(y)(w) \\ & \href{/posts/arithmetic-made-difficult/Composition.html#thm-compose2on1} = & f(g(x)(y))(h(z)(w)) \end{eqnarray*}\] as claimed.

Testing

Suite:

_test_compose ::
  ( Equal a, Show a, Arbitrary a, CoArbitrary a, TypeName a
  , Equal b, Show b, Arbitrary b, CoArbitrary b, TypeName b
  , Equal c, Show c, Arbitrary c, CoArbitrary c, TypeName c
  , Equal d, Show d, Arbitrary d, CoArbitrary d, TypeName d
  , Equal e, Show e, Arbitrary e, CoArbitrary e, TypeName e
  , Equal f, Show f, Arbitrary f, CoArbitrary f, TypeName f
  , Equal g, Show g, Arbitrary g, CoArbitrary g, TypeName g
  ) => Int -> Int -> a -> b -> c -> d -> e -> f -> g -> IO ()

_test_compose size cases a b c d e f g = do
  testLabel0 "compose"
  let args = testArgs size cases

  runTest args (_test_compose1on2 a b c d)
  runTest args (_test_compose1on3 a b c d e)
  runTest args (_test_compose1on4 a b c d e f)
  runTest args (_test_compose2on1 a b c d e)
  runTest args (_test_compose2on2 a b c d e f g)
  runTest args (_test_compose3on1 a b c d e f g)

Main:

main_compose :: IO ()
main_compose = do
  _test_compose 1 1 () () () () () () ()